The Influence of Moral Particularism in Law and Ethics
Submitting Institution
University of ReadingUnit of Assessment
PhilosophySummary Impact Type
LegalResearch Subject Area(s)
Philosophy and Religious Studies: Philosophy
Summary of the impact
Prof. Jonathan Dancy has over several decades developed the theory of
ethical particularism, culminating in seminal publications dating from his
time at the University of Reading, most notably his magnum opus Ethics
Without Principles (2004). Particularism has had an impact within the
legal profession, not just among legal scholars but on practitioners
themselves, even to the extent of its being applied in judicial
decision-making. It has also, partly through serendipitous means
capitalised upon by Dancy himself, found its way into public ethical
debate — directly contributing to the enrichment of civil society and
stimulation of cultural life by introducing non-academics to a powerful
and provocative new view of morality.
Underpinning research
Dancy (Reading 1996-2011, 2013-2016, also part time at University of
Texas, Austin) is the `father figure' of ethical particularism, the theory
that there are no moral principles for the guidance of action (a theory
with its historical roots in the intuitionist tradition). Ethical
generalists, as they are often called, believe that to be a moral person
you must know and act on principles, which at their strongest are
exceptionless commands and prohibitions, such as `Love your neighbour' and
`Don't steal'. Without moral principles there can be no difference between
right and wrong, and no hope for an agent to be fully virtuous.
Over several decades of sustained research, Dancy has argued forcefully
against this traditional view of moral reasoning. He holds that there are
moral principles in the sense of rules of thumb, maxims, counsels, etc.,
but their function is not to guide action in an invariable way across
circumstances. Rather, a feature of a situation that makes an act, say,
wrong in one case may work differently in another situation to make that
act right. That A has taken B's property without permission does not
invariably contravene the supposed principle against theft, though it is a
feature of the case that usually counts against what A did, even if not
overwhelmingly. If B's property is a samurai sword and B is insane, it
would be right for A to take it off him without consent if he can. But if
B is sane and the sword is a mere ornament hanging harmlessly on B's wall,
taking it without permission would be theft.
References to the research
The body of research has been externally peer-reviewed and assessed as of
at least 2* quality
Books:
1. Practical Reality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000), pp. 187;
paperback edition published 2002.
2. Ethics Without Principles (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004), pp.
229; paperback edition 2006.
Articles:
3. `Defending Particularism', in Metaphilosophy vol. 30, nos 1-2,
Jan/April 1999, pp. 25-32.
4. 'The Particularist's Progress', in B. W. Hooker and M. Little eds. Moral
Particularism (OUP 2000), pp. 130-56; reprinted in T.
Rønnow-Rasmussen and M. Zimmerman eds. Intrinsic Value
(Kluwer/Springer), 2006.
5. 'Enticing Reasons', in Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral
Philosophy of Joseph Raz, ed. R. Jay Wallace, Philip Pettit, Samuel
Scheffler, and Michael Smith (OUP 2004), pp. 91-118; reprinted in C. Nimtz
and A. Beckermann eds. Philosophy — Science — Scientific Philosophy.
Main Lectures and Colloquia of GAP.5, Fifth International Congress
of the Society for Analytical Philosophy, (Paderborn: MENTIS, 2005) pp.
10-32.
6. `McDowell, Williams and Intuitionism', in Luck, Value and
Commitment: Themes from the Ethics of Bernard Williams eds. U. Heuer
and G. Lang (OUP, 2012).
Details of the impact
Ethical particularism is important in this case study because it is now
being discussed and debated within the legal profession, not just among
scholars but also practitioners. Specifically, tort lawyers have taken
cognizance of ethical particularism in the context of whether and to what
extent negligence determinations should be left to a jury, given the
variation of features across similar cases and the impossibility of
proposing hard and fast negligence rules.
In addition, particularism has become an important part of general
ethical debate among the public. This has partly arisen serendipitously,
via opportunities presented to Dancy, and capitalised on by him, to
publicise his research to a broad audience. He has on various occasions
presented his theory in an accessible way to non-academics, using concrete
examples of moral reasoning to illustrate abstract ideas in an engaging
and provocative way — especially the clash between our belief in
exceptionless general principles of morality, and our willingness to make
exceptions and qualifications in particular cases
Impact on the legal profession
Dancy's particularist theory has — in a way that is rare for the work of
a philosopher who is not a jurisprude — entered legal discourse as a
theory to be taken seriously in helping lawyers understand recent and past
rulings.
The most important evidence of the impact of particularism in the law
comes from the American Law Institute's (ALI's) Restatement of the Law of
Torts, 3rd edition, pub. 2010. ALI Restatements are internationally
recognised as highly significant legal documents. They are essentially
codifications of case law, i.e. common law judge-made doctrines that
develop gradually over time. Although Restatements are not binding
authority in and of themselves, they reflect the consensus of the American
legal community as to what the law is (and in some areas, what it should
become). There are then good grounds for viewing the Restatements as the
most influential secondary authority in this area. The above Restatement
(Ch.3 sec.8) says: `Tort law has thus accepted an ethics of particularism,
which tends to cast doubt on the viability of general rules capable of
producing determinate results and which requires that actual moral
judgments be based on the circumstances of each individual situation. Tort
law's affirmation of this requirement highlights the primary role
necessarily fulfilled by the jury.'
The citation for this passage names Dancy as the progenitor of
particularism and refers to a paper of his from 1983. It is extremely rare
for a contemporary philosopher to receive mention in an ALI Restatement
(indeed we are aware of no other examples). Although this citation refers
to a very early publication which predates Dancy's employment at Reading,
it is clear that it is the theory of particularism itself, developed over
several decades and reaching its mature and complete form in 2004, that
has led to the impact here, as opposed to a single early paper. This
assumption has been confirmed by email correspondence with the lawyer in
charge of the project. Furthermore, it is worth stressing that this impact
is on legal practice itself, not merely on academic discussion. The theory
of particularism is providing part of the intellectual toolkit by which
legal practitioners conceptualise and structure their domain, with ensuing
changes and benefits to practice and understanding amongst this community.
- The reach of particularism into judicial practice is also discussed in
a paper in the Hofstra Law Review, 2008. Here an academic lawyer argues
that a preference for particularism explains the way in which judges
decide certain cases and he makes explicit reference numerous times to
Dancy. Again, the point to stress here is that it is the judges and
lawyers on whom particularism is held to have had an influence, even if
it may be through the medium of academic legal interpretation: the
decisions judges reach are being shaped by, and can best be understood
by practitioners in terms of, ethical particularism.
- Finally, a recent US Supreme Court decision, Hosanna-Tabor (2012) has
received much discussion amongst legal experts. One blog, Mirror of
Justice, discusses it at some length, with the author, a legal academic,
referring to the work of Dancy and `judicial particularism' as a way of
interpreting the decision. This leads to posts by a non-academic (as it
seems) debating the issue with the author
(http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2012/01/what-does-it-mean-to-call-a-judicial-opinion-particularist.html).
If
the interpretation by the original post's author is correct, then it can
also be claimed with plausibility that particularism has influenced the
Supreme Court justices themselves, even if they have not heard of Dancy
by name.
- Given the influence and importance of ALI Restatements and the
recentness of this evidence of impact, we think it reasonable to suggest
that the impact seen thus far, though significant in its own right, also
constitutes only the initial stages of potential impact. The Department
is committed to working closely with Dancy to consolidate the impact of
his research in this crucial area, ensuring maximum reach for his
important philosophical work.
General impact outside academia
Dancy's research has also found its way into the arena of general public
debate about morality:
- Dancy, extremely unusually for a professional philosopher, was invited
to appear on a popular TV show in 2010. His interview on the US
late-night talk show The Late Late Show with Craig Ferguson (audience
1.4 million) was devoted almost entirely to explaining moral
particularism to a general audience, which Dancy did admirably well. Not
only was the interviewer enthralled, but follow-up comments on the
Internet show non-academics engaging with the topic. Ferguson himself
joked that the research was just the thing to appeal to the 18-35 `kids'
in his audience demographic.
- The cultural reach of moral particularism is also evidenced by a
lengthy discussion, with Dancy prominently named, in a 2013 article for
the digital magazine Aeon (which `seeks to invigorate conversations
about worldviews...open to diverse perspectives and committed to
progressive social change'). The discussion has thus far generated 62
comments from interested lay readers (http://tinyurl.com/ompx87e),
together with 1000 `likes' on Facebook and 200 tweets.
- Members of the public engaged with Colin Allen and Jonathan Dancy in
general ethical debate about whether there could be `moral machines' in
the blog On The Human (2011). Allen, an academic, tries to use Dancy's
particularism (cited by name) in the context of defending the
possibility of `moral machines' or `moral robots' capable of responding
to novel and variable moral situations rather than being programmed
(impossibly) to follow general principles. This leads to a response by
Dancy himself, debating with Allen over the extent of their
agreement/disagreement, as well as a number of non-academics weighing in
with various opinions about particularism and the possibility of moral
machines.
- A blog for discussion of theology and philosophy of religion (2010)
contains posts by non-academics discussing moral particularism, with
Dancy mentioned by name. His Stanford Encyclopaedia article on moral
particularism is cited, as well as the Wikipedia entry on him.
- Finally, Dancy's Philosophy Bites podcast (a series aimed at
presenting philosophical research in a format accessible for
non-specialists), discussing moral particularism, has been downloaded
nearly 49,000 times. We can very safely be sure that the vast majority
of downloaders are non-academics for whom the podcasts are designed.
Again, we take this as evidence that his work has helped to inform and
shape views about morality among this group.
Beneficiaries
Lawyers are now seeing particularism as a way of understanding judicial
determinations, especially in negligence cases (see for instance the
discussion of the decisions made by Justice Stevens at http://www.scotusblog.com/2010/04/justice-stevens-particularist/).
It has caused them to reflect on whether general principles can actually
determine a decision in factually similar cases.
Members of the public who have expressed opinions about the theory are
divided as to its strength. Some see it as a challenge to the very idea of
objectivity in ethics, others as a welcome alternative to a rigorously
rule-based application of morality to various situations. Some have
clearly been stimulated to apply particularist thinking to their own
specific concerns. All are provoked and challenged by the theory to think
more deeply about the content of an ethical system.
Reach and significance
It is hard to think of a much more significant impact on the American
legal profession than being mentioned in an ALI Restatement. Together with
the articles and online discussion cited above, we think this can ground a
claim for the highly significant reach of particularism in the profession.
Furthermore we know from a 2010 Wake Forest Law Review study that nearly
one third of US Supreme Court decisions cite academic articles published
in law reviews (http://www.abajournal.com/magazine/article/the_high_bench_vs._the_ivory_tower/),
suggesting that the impact of particularism is also being enhanced by its
discussion in academic legal journals. As far as wider cultural impact is
concerned, as with most philosophy it is hard to assess the number of
people influenced by a position or theory. The Craig Ferguson show
regularly attracts around 1.4 million viewers, of whom one can be certain
that thousands would at least have been challenged by the interview to
think more about ethical decision-making. Again, intensity of influence is
difficult to measure. Some viewers were sufficiently interested to read up
on particularism, especially Dancy's article in the Stanford
Encyclopaedia; one found the theory `very appealing' and wondered whether
further reading might `keep me from sleeping tonight'.
Evidence
In the case of Dancy's impact on legal reasoning in general and judicial
reasoning in particular, the evidence is that cited above. Furthermore,
there are a significant number of references to Dancy's work on ethical
particularism in various other legal journals, including his most recent
work such as the 2004 book, as well as secondary literature discussing his
theory. These include The Supreme Court Review (2004), The Stanford Law
Review (2002), The University of Chicago Law Review (2008), The Modern Law
Review (2005), and The Oxford Journal of Legal Studies (2009).
There are two points to make about this evidence. First, all of these
publications are contributed to and read by legal academics, who then
disseminate the ideas at conferences and workshops, where they often
become the common currency of debate within the legal profession itself.
We cannot prove that judicial particularist leanings in various decisions
such as Hosanna-Tabor were informed by ideas that originated in academic
journals. Judges do not usually cite academic works or opinions in their
decisions (but see above concerning the US Supreme Court). Nor, however,
do their interpretations of the law emanate from nothing more than their
personal and idiosyncratic predilections. Rather, their judicial work is
informed by, and taps into, the existing climate of debate over
interpretation, policy, the use of precedent, etc. This debate is to a
large extent shaped by the original work of academic specialists, some of
whom are practitioners themselves. Secondly, judges and legal
practitioners read academic journals and are directly informed by their
contents. We are therefore confident that Dancy's particularism has had an
impact, albeit indirect and via academic discussion in legal journals, on
non-academic thinking in the legal profession.
In the case of Dancy's work as it pertains to the wider community, there
can be no doubt that particularism has become a lively topic of discussion
among philosophically interested members of the public. The examples above
are typical. And here is a TV critic for Entertainment Weekly commenting
on Dancy's appearance on the Craig Ferguson show:
"True to his desire, Ferguson hosted a segment with Dancy last night. May
I say that I not only found it a more entertaining segment than the one
that had preceded it — someone named Robin Williams was the first guest —
but that I want to take a class with Professor Dancy right now? Dancy is a
very big cheese in his field. [He] came very close to making a dunderhead
like me understand what he was getting at in making distinctions between
right and wrong and the context in which such terms have meaning. If, say,
PBS still stood for what it used to (that is, educational programming for
the good of the nation rather than a few good shows sprinkled into a
schedule of antiquing and repair series), Jonathan Dancy would be doing
for moral particularism what Robert Hughes once did for modern art in The
Shock of the New: teaching us via vivid language and examples. I found
Prof. Dancy exhilarating. How about you?"
(http://watching-tv.ew.com/2010/04/02/craig-ferguson-jonathan-dancy-claire-danes/,
2 April 2010).
There follow 79 comments, quite a few of them mentioning Dancy. Typical
comments include: `I was so confounded during that interview and at the
same time, I didn't want it to end' and `I felt as if I had been invited
to sit in on a conversation rather than being "performed" to, which was
down to both Ferguson and Dancy.'
Sources to corroborate the impact
(Contact details for individuals below provided separately)
The Late Late Show with Craig Ferguson, CBS Corporation
Editor At Large for Entertainment Weekly (Commenting upon Dancy's Late
Late Show appearance and its impact on television viewers who read his
widely influential blog)
Associate Professor of Law, St John's University (The impact of
particularism on judicial decision-making and legal practice)
Professor of Law, Indiana University (The impact of particularism on
judicial decision-making and legal practice)
David and Mary Harrison Distinguished Professor of Law, University of
Virginia (The impact of particularism on judicial decision-making and
legal practice)